Time is a central aspect of Narrative, and Narrative is the primary filter through which we view things, so it makes sense that we speak of Time as if it were actually a phenomenon, part of Nature. But Time does not actually exist.
There seems to be more and more recognition about this in various pockets around academia - among psychologists, narratologists and physicists, for example - but the recent conversations are so specialized and diverse at the moment that perusing abstracts and conference summaries about all the related angles and research sub-topics is a bewildering reading experience, and that's just scratching the surface. Someday, before too many more decades pass by, we will probably see a major work become popularized (among scholars) that will AT LEAST begin to establish the basic fact that Time is not what we might think it is. Lord, haste the day.
There are no parallel universes. I'll bet you infinite dollars. However, if there was such a thing, I'd like to think that my humble offering, below, might have served well in one alternate universe as the helpful beginning of such a groundbreaking popular book. Ah, fantasies... okay, so those kind of alt-uni's do exist, in our minds, but now I really digress.
For what it's worth, here is the beginning of an early draft manuscript for a book project that, I am relatively certain, I will never attempt to complete. This is merely one of the sacrifices that's been demanded of me by my brain and my keyboard, sometime over the past six or nine months. There are a few others. This may need to happen again, soon.
Without further ado, I release here, stillborn, onto the internets, my partial draft of a book about Time.
Enjoy.
*****************************************
Understanding Time
Introduction – What is Time?
Chapter One – When Time Began
Chapter Two – Physics and Poetry
Chapter Three – Ideas that are not Things
*****************************************************************
INTRODUCTION – What is Time?
Time does not exist, except as an idea. Time is
not a real thing. Time is a concept. Time is a word we use to compare relative
motion, to predict naturally repetitive occurrences, and to anticipate
regularized human activity. But time, itself, is only the idea in our heads,
drawn from all our methods of accounting for movement and change.
Time does not pass. Things happen and we speak
of time having passed. But there was no time any place, no thing that could
pass from one place to another. Things changed. Stuff moved around. The sky lit
up and went dark and lit up once again. So we say, "Time passed". But
time did not pass because time does not exist.
Time is not something we travel through. Land,
sea and air travel are possible because physical locations exist perpetually.
To travel from China to France is as easy as returning from France back to
China because both locations persist in the physical realm. Neighbors can walk
back and forth between houses because both houses continue to exist, both
perpetually and simultaneously. In contrast, however, no one “travels” from
moment to moment. Nobody departs from a location called “five thirty pm” and
propels themselves to arrive at a different temporal realm called “five thirty
one pm”.
This is why time travel
will always remain science fiction alone, which illustrates a very serious
point. The reason people will never leave 2014 and “travel” to the year 1814 is
because there is no "meta-temporal realm" within which 2014 and 1814 might
each be located, as if existing both perpetually and simultaneously. In fact,
by definition, 2014 does not exist, and 1814 does not persist. For the year 1814 to be
reachable would require it to be locatable, as if it still exists, in some
magical place, somehow.
For that matter, even talking
about "the year 1814" is a profoundly strange concept, in the first
place. What do we know about 1814? For starters, what happened? There was one
particular orbit around our Sun during which lots of happenings transpired.
People moved around. Stuff changed. Seasons revolved. But that was no different
than the cycle before.
Nothing marked the end of "1813"
except a conventional technique of our storytelling. There was no
"1814". And when the calendar said 1815, there was no new reality, no
new "point" at which everyone had arrived. It was not suddenly any
new "time". Some labels had changed, some conceptions had changed,
and some circumstances had changed, but this was entirely incidental. There was
no aspect of reality which, itself, became different. Not on January 1st or any
other day.
There is no such thing as time, except in the
way we tell stories.
In this physical universe,
all we have is motion and change.
But speaking of stories and the universe, how
does all this affect our understanding of God?
If God exists, we presume God can act and cause
change - to create, to sustain life, to affect history. In other words, we
presume God can move. But can God be moved? Can God be changed? Those questions
may be unsettling, but the real problem is that they are, frankly, too vague.
To rephrase more specifically, we might rather ask – What in God's universe
might move, change or affect God? When someone names a power that strong, I'll
believe God has changed. I mean, what human being thinks they are mighty enough
to be sincerely concerned about altering God? Isn’t it reasonable to admit that
what most people fear most is not whether or not they can change God, but
whether God might attempt to change them?
I suspect this goes double
for anyone in religious authority. To speak of God and yet have control over
things must engender some dread about whether God might step in and change the
way things get run around here. I suspect that is why those authorities
presented us with a timeless, changeless, motionless, immobile God. He exists
"outside of time". All that is yet to be has already been done. All
is as He prefers. Do not question the men in the big hats who can read books.
God wants you to work, give, breed and die - or, in other words, the men in
charge want you to be just as changeless as God is.
But what if we don't want to be ruled by those
men? And what if we don't want to take over their place, either?
Suppose somebody actually wanted to be ruled by
God. Suppose that God wanted to actually rule that person directly. In order
for that to actually happen, wouldn't God need to act? To move? To cause
change?
The usual authorities tend to answer these
questions by explaining that God is "outside time" and yet God
"acts within time". But all this does is create a pretend boundary,
which on our side remains largely and mercifully God Free. The truth is that a
lot of religious authorities want and need to keep God on the other side, “outside
time”. We, ourselves, are the ones God expects to do all the things around
here. Now, give us your money. It’s time for the sermon.
….
But what if I could show that none of this is
true? And what if I could prove this not by arguing philosophically about the
nature of God but by arguing scientifically about the nature of
"Time"?
God is neither within time nor beyond time. God
cannot be "outside of time" or "inside time". This is not
because God cannot do such things. This is because time does not really exist.
Time is not a thing that God should be within it
or beyond it.
Time is a perfectly human
idea.
*****************************************************************
CHAPTER ONE - When Time Began
Time is nothing but an idea, a brilliant effort
to project order onto chaos. It's actually easy to see how such an effort first
started.
The natural world generates so much
unpredictable movement and so much unsettling change that people had to come up
with reliable ways of anticipating those things, to be ready for something, to
respond or prepare, and to act upon things instead of merely being acted upon.
To survive and to thrive, humans deduced various methods of accounting for
motion and change.
The most basic measurement, as always, as it is
still today, was one-to-one correlation. Instead of measuring with a line on a
stick, or with dials going around circles, the precise times for things were
measured by other actual things.
The fishing was better when the river was at
medium height. The dinner was ready when the meat had changed color. The baby
would come when a mother's belly was large. The most obvious correlations were
the earliest ones to be noted, and valued, as reliable ways to anticipate change
and predict future events. It was basic needs that developed this primitive method
of “measuring time”.
Some of these notable changes recurred
cyclically in nature. Certain animals were best hunted at night. Certain
seasons made clouds more likely to rain. Winter thawing brought strong rivers.
Falling leaves showed the air would get colder. Dawn or midday might provide
extra safety for collecting water or berries, in the rivers and forests. The
repetition of all these correlations was the only reassuring consistency in our
dealings with nature, and that ongoing repetitive aspect in human anticipating
eventually led to a more sophisticated adaptation.
The natural objects of motion that changed
position most predictably came from on high. The moon gave us months, and in
some places, tides. The sun gave us days, its north or southerliness gave us
seasons, which, being repeated, made years. An encouraging factor in all this
was the numeric consistency. There were always so many days to a moon, give or
take one day, and always so many moons to a year, more or less one moon. And while
the seasons fought one another during transition, there were always two extreme
times of the year. Things got colder. Things got warmer. The pattern kept on
repeating.
While tides rose and fell
on the coast in a less symmetrical cycle, there was nevertheless one high tide
and one low tide, without fail, every day. There was no concept of “time” until
someone sat back and thought about all these things as a concept. In the typical
daily subsistence, there was only an awareness of what happened and what
helped. These repetitive motions were important because they made some things
predictable.
The more consistent the motion, and the more
reliable it's predictive correlations, the more comforting it felt for the
earliest humans in the midst of their catch-as-catch-can daily fight to
survive. In fact, the life saving providential powers of these natural cycles
were so comforting that ancient ideas about God were universally tied to these
celestial objects in some way or another. Either God was the Cosmos or God
created the cosmos, but in either case one inescapable idea was of Creator as
giver of life, because his creation sustains us with orderly facets, despite
its chaotic aspects. Likewise, as order was most powerfully found in the
heavens, so God and his wisdom must also be in the heavens.
Astrology proved unreliable, but its fundamental
attractiveness to any primitive people was based on the fascinating combination
of constant and variable motions being displayed in the stars. Just like on
earth, some things were predictable and other things weren’t. The intrigue
began when someone learned how to see long term patterns in planetary motion,
which had seemed wildly irregular on a month to month basis. Thus, the
superstition arose that perhaps unpredictable behaviors down here were also
predictable. It might have seemed obvious that stars and planets did not
determine which earthly happenings come to pass in our lives, but the appeal remained
powerful as human need remained severe, and that is the key point to remember. In
its origins, astrology was nothing more than another human attempt to discern
measurable predictability in a world full of motion and change.
We can similar things about other parts of our histories,
and see similar things keep on going today. Any time we look with such primitive
eyes at the intersection of variable circumstance and human behavior, most
things we do seem oriented around getting or keeping control over
uncontrollable things. Overall, when you look closely at anyone who's being
successful at maintaining an ongoing arrangement, at any level of complexity,
one of the most basic aspects is schedule. To maintain control over anything
for a decent period of time one must keep careful track of how those things
tend move over time. The central issue is always basic need. Even today, if
Wal-Mart could manage their shipping and retail empire with astrology they'd
have no compunctions against doing so. As it happens, of course, modern methods
are more effective at scheduling, workflow, inventory, and so forth. The best
method is whatever works.
With that in mind, let's get back to basic
methods and primitive people. The first really powerful tool in the whole
history of mankind was a mental tool. It was actually a concept. Very, very
early into the game, people had to swap out from thinking about change and swap
in to thinking about "time", as if time was a thing. If you wanted to
control an environment full of change, you needed some way to grapple with
time.
That is, early notions of "time" were
developed so that people could stop merely comparing endless pairs of
particular things (the world's too exhausting on a one-to-one basis), and so
people could begin using more systematic methods of accounting for change. In
turn, this led to more successful methods for engineering change and/or
prohibiting change. These have always been our primary motivations for thinking
about "Time". Even when we can’t control all change, it helps that we're
at least keeping track.
One early success in advanced temporal
accounting was to track the sun's daily motion by shadow length. Your own
shadow, if you pay it a lot of attention, can be almost as good as a sundial.
Much later on, people invented actual sundials, though the first ones weren’t
very precise. Eventually someone discovered these could be most practical when
quartered and then subdivided again. Now, quartering was efficient – two halves
of two halves, day and night halved again – but each quarter was then trebled.
Evidently twelve "hours" was judged to be more workable than eight or
sixteen. Twelve also held some appeal because most years had twelve moons, and
from twelve lines on the clock we put twelve zodiac signs in the sky. (Seven
days of the week appears to be based on the number of visible planets, God’s
activity in Genesis notwithstanding, I suppose.)
To appreciate just how
abstract and how arbitrary is our system of “time”, let’s linger a while on the
development of clocks. Modern folks are so familiar with hours and minutes that
we think of these concepts as if they were actual things. Rather, hours and
minutes are distinct cultural inventions. First, that initial decision to
quarter the sundial is why modern clocks don’t have ten hours, or any other
division. Think about this. That shadow moves all the way around that little
round dial without caring how many lines anybody had drawn on it. As for
minutes, the sundial was never precise enough, which is why minutes didn’t
exist until European clockmakers invented that concept during the Renaissance.
Once they started using gears to move a bar around that circle, it became easy
to add more gears and get another bar that would move around faster. The minute
hand is the <my newt> hand, pronounced that way because it was so much
smaller. When a third bar was added to cycle even more quickly, they made it
even smaller, and so it was the second <my newt> hand, and thus we began
measuring "seconds", even though the second hand is the third arm on
a clock. Truly, if they hadn’t chosen the word “minute”, we might today keep
track of hours and seconds and thirds.
Think about sixty seconds. The number sixty, of
course, is a multiple of twelve. All three hands had to go around the same dial
and counting multiples was more practical than the other option - which
involved fractions. (Be grateful!) Also, sixty is obviously a multiple of ten.
By the time of the Renaissance, "five" and "ten" had become
bigger concepts than they had been for ancient folks, partly due to an
advancing self-centrism (including the number of our digits) and partly due to
advances in mathematics. But even if this had developed during the Roman Age
(V, X, C?) they could just as easily have decided to standardize clock faces
with forty-eight minutes per hour, and forty-eight seconds per minute (12x4).
Or, it could have been seventy-two (12x6).
It should begin to seem clear, now, how
arbitrary this all is. These "things" we call minutes and seconds are
just concepts, nothing more than ideas invented by gear heads, invented and
then kept because they proved first to be interesting, and then to be useful.
Or perhaps you already knew about most of this? Either way, the important point
is that everything about our basic concept of time is based on real experience
and observable motion, but the development of "time" and its increments
remain nothing more than human ideas.
It doesn’t matter how
sophisticated this concept has become or continues to be. Time is not a part of
the universe, per se. Time is merely a word that we use as an efficient means
of describing how we perceive a whole world (and universe) filled with
observable motion and change.
The fact that minutes and seconds didn't exist
until technology advanced during the Renaissance should illustrate that our
concept of “minutes” is artificial. But although our concept of days and years
is based on natural experience, is a “day” any more real? Can anyone hold onto
a “year”?
Like Time itself, all
these measurable units of "time" are simply ideas people made up.
Let's have some fun with this. Imagine back even
earlier - if sundials had become standardized with eight or sixteen lines
(instead of twelve) then watch faces today would probably contain eighty or
sixty-four minutes. And each of those minutes would contain eighty or
sixty-four seconds. Now, bring that back into our time. A timekeeping world
based on that sundial might have made which my quarter mile run time sound more
(or less) impressive back in High School, it might have made a sit-com last
forty (or twenty-four) minutes, and it would have taken four minutes (or two
minutes, alternatively), to boil a three minute egg.
In all seriousness, please take note.
Timekeeping is not therefore absurd. Timekeeping is therefore arbitrary.
Even better, imagine if someone had invented the
decimal system a few thousand years earlier. In such a world, today, physics
equations would be easier because an "hour" would contain precisely
100 minutes, which seems logical, even though watchmakers would have developed
arthritis more quickly from carving in all those tiny lines. In a world that
developed from metric system sundials, you'd never think of taking a fifteen
minute break because our clocks wouldn't have been arbitrarily quartered, but a
"half-hour" would have been fifty minutes in length, and you could
automatically calculate your hourly pay, by the minute, to the penny! That
might also give us a lot fewer accountants, but I'll allow you to decide if
that's a good or a bad thing.
The point bears repeating. As modern people,
we're all so accustomed to these numbers - 12, 24, 60 - that we live day to day
without realizing how arbitrary and artificial they are.
Guys get excited when a new sports car goes
"zero to sixty" in a certain number of "seconds". But it's
all purely random. Except that the next sports car can be measured
comparatively to other sports cars. Yours does five point eight? Well mine does
five point two! And that's the real point of all measurement. Comparison.
Wondrously, that sports car analogy is no
different than the ancient impulse to hunt or fish or gather or plant - because
to do any of those things well, it was best to do each thing at a particular
time. What modern measurement does is it systematizes the usefulness of one to
one correlation, and thus indirect comparison. But measurement began with the
earliest of us all.
Moons bring the tide. Winter brings rain, or
snow. Each new sports car has to outpace the last. These days, most
time-measured correlations are focused on human customs, or human inventions.
As ancient people discovered useful reasons to keep track of their
"hours" (or at least for sometimes speaking as if they were actually
doing so) modern people advanced in their measuring power by using more precise
instruments. Without the sundial, we don't get the clock, so we don't get
minutes & seconds, so we get less precise physics equations, and perhaps we
don't ever get to walk on the moon. But with minutes and seconds, our precise
scientific observation of Speed becomes feasible and eventually productive.
Remember, all measurement is comparison. Like
the finer concepts in Geometry and Calculus, these precise units of
"Time" are just an intellectual construct that makes comparison
possible, so that physics equations can be written and so that scientists can
give names to observable aspects of natural phenomena.
Scientific description, by the way, is a
bonafide literary art. Science actually works quite well with poetry or
fiction. Like all fields of knowledge, scientists build narratives. They tell
stories about what they think the whole universe is like. Science is right to
have literature. Science depends upon literature. What can be surprisingly
difficult is to know which is which.
In Physics, words stand for powerful concepts.
Velocity. Acceleration. Force. Momentum. These are beautifully descriptive
names we've assigned to the general results of countless experimental
equations, none of which would have ever been possible without pioneering
innovations in human concepts about time. To be sure, the concepts of power and
speed were deduced eons ago. But the concepts of Acceleration and Force? When
considered as specific phenomena that are both measurable and quantifiable? No.
The physical effects are obviously very real but the scientific description is
an intellectual construction, not unlike fiction. The most basic terminology in
just scientists finding very creative ways to be precisely effective in
describing how one thing in motion compares, in some way, to another thing in
motion. Your plane flies at Mach One? Well my prototype doubled that, um, a few
moments before it disintegrated. It all works, and it's all mathematically
beautiful, but it's all built on intensely sophisticated methods of comparing
one motion to another. Is Mach one a slow speed? Einstein suggested such labels
are relative. He said, "Time is relative." Like velocity itself, for
a physicist, time is a contrived system for comparative measurement.
Of course time is relative. All measurement is
comparative.
Are we agreed yet? Time does not actually exist.
It's a human idea. Minutes are not things which exist, neither now nor before
clocks were invented. By the same token, a "day" is not a thing that
exists. Days are simply and merely a useful concept for distinguishing our
plans and our memories from our present experience. So are years.
So if "time" really doesn't exist,
what do we *think* it is?
*****************************************************************
CHAPTER TWO - Physics and Poetry
Let's begin considering "What is
Time?" by first asking, what is Physics? The short answer is, Physics is a
complex ideological construction.
To speak more carefully, Physics is absolutely
and completely real, but our analysis of it is very largely contrived. And of
course that's just fine. This is a bit like how the word "History"
refers either to the actual past *or* to a written account in which someone
describes the past. By "Physics" we can sometimes refer to the
physical world in which planets orbit and spin, in which rivers run, tides rise
and hunters hunt, shooting bullets to deadly effect, no matter how we measure
(or attempt to describe) such grave power. Also, by "Physics", we can
also refer to the social world in which professional professors profess to us
about ideas like Newtonian mechanics and Einsteinian relativity and something
called "string theory".
Personally, I can't begin to explain anything
about string theory but I know it does not mean the universe is actually made
up of strings. We all know what strings are: things like shoe strings, guitar
strings and banana strings. They are tiny things, to be tied, to be plucked, to
be thrown in the trash. But any good Physicist, if pressed, will tell you that
something about their conception of the universe has some aspect about it which
reminds them in some way of strings. And at that point we're discussing more
than phenomena. With the central metaphor of string theory, we're suddenly
discussing both phenomena and poetics.
Poetry, like Physics, is another worthwhile
example of a complex ideological construction. So is History (in that second
sense). So is Political Science. And more. While Chemistry and Physics can at
least claim to engage measurable phenomenon, they still wind up producing
complex ideological constructions, like the Bohr model of an atom, which is not
actually an atom, or like the Periodic table of elements, which fails to
demonstrate anything concrete about elements, such as why matter can seem so
structurally similar at this well-organized atomic level and yet so wildly
differentiated in all of its various physical forms. This is sometimes called
the Paradox of Models. In all fields, there is that which is, and then there is
our perceptive ability, and then there is our attempt at description. And what
do we call creative writers who try to capture the essence of phenomena in mere
words? In so many profound ways, all of science depends upon poetry.
Consider the community of Poets, which has
rarely considered analyzing their craft scientifically. Despite that, what
poets do us attempt to capture with words what ought to be indescribable - what
it's actually like to have experiences and emotions that are particularly
human. There may be no precise type of accounting for a phenomenon like Walt
Whitman or even Emily Dickenson, and yet, in the simplest measurement terms of
one-to-one correlation, a listener or reader often finds a particular poem can
cause something inside them to resonate powerfully. Thomas Nagel said we don't
know what it's like to be a bat, but if a bat screech resonated inside us like
a good poem does, then Nagel would have been incorrect. There's just something
*that* mysterious about someone else's experience.
I don't know what it's like to be Judy Garland,
yet biographers can attempt to explain her life to me so that I might
understand Judy Garland. But my capacity for understanding her is probably
somewhere on a scale of comprehensibility, that runs from understanding a bat,
to understanding a poem, to understanding inertia, to understanding a river. Or
the sunrise. Some things we understand by observation and some things we cannot
ever surmise. There are good basic answers that explain why water rains from
the sky, or why Cleopatra was successful (until Mark Antony failed), and why
more people butter their toast than use jelly or jam. But there are other
things we probably cannot ever hope to fully explain, like Judy Garland, or
interstellar gravitation, or World War II, or why the sky is blue *really*.
There will always be aspects of most studies about which we may always be
guessing.
So, obviously, there is certainty and then there
is guessing. But in terms of practical value for living today, what can be most
confusing, or at least most unhelpful, is to get one category confused with the
other. Sometimes people sound certain about things where they are at least
partly guessing. Other times, people sound uncertain about things which,
depending on circumstances, really ought to be pretty discernable. In the hopes
of better living on earth - and for more accurate meta-analysis in research -
we need to try and identify known-unknowns, while preventing ourselves from
replacing those blank spots with false knowledge.
Like biographers, poets and historians, who are
non-systematic researchers, chemists and physicists are merely, and ultimately,
attempting to describe things that profoundly challenge description. The
discovery of DNA wasn't very important until its well written description by
Watson & Crick made many more people pay attention, because DNA suddenly
seemed like a thing that was possible to understand.
Point: Science without Poetry would be pretty
darn useless.
Counter-point: We should never confuse Poetry
for Science.
By the nature of their various fields, some
researchers get to use a greater proportion of hard data in cooking and serving
up the ingredients of their larger considerations, and other researchers have
less opportunity to be working from what we might call 'tangible certainties'.
Regardless, there is some science in all art and there is some art in all
science. We do very well if we learn how to recognize that.
Getting back to the point...
Time, it so happens, is one subject about which
people get very confused. Is time a real thing? Or is time invented, like
guesswork?
Or is it possible, in some way, that time is
both art and science, so to speak? Could it be that Time is both a real
phenomenon *and* an intellectual construct, like Physics and History?
A lot of people think so, but I have a different
opinion...
*****************************************************************
CHAPTER THREE - Ideas that are not things.
*****building from earlier section, or deleting
it......
or like our standardized system of measurable
units called Time. But the field or genre or topic of Poetry is, itself, an
innovated construction.
In all the history of language and written
communication, what makes a sonnet a poem? Can a soup label be poetry? It all
depends whom you ask. But all the prominently received answers to those
questions come together in a vast and complicated tradition of all
professionals who've ever made their living off "Poetry". Sincerely,
now, please note my lack of cynicism about this. I am not saying they're wrong.
I'm saying they've taken part in shaping and upholding this enormous
intellectual construct of rules and exceptions about what considerations might
qualify my paragraph, here, to be labeled as Poetry". Or not.
Likewise, I wouldn't say Economists are
necessarily full of hot air - at least, not all the time - but what they're all
working on, collectively, is still attempting to become more alchemy-free, so
to speak. What I mean is, they can all be dedicated economists who work with
noble intentions toward what might yet become even more effective at
understanding financial and market behavior, but their whole game remains
something they've had to make up as they went along.
And that's fine. But is Economics an actual
thing? Or is it *merely* an idea? Is Poetry really a thing, in the way that
Gravity and History and Chemistry are really actual phenomena? Economics might
be a fair term for a general set of phenomena, if broadly defined. But you
cannot pick up a transaction and say, here, this is Economics! More
categorically, Poetry is not a real thing at all. It's an abstract idea.
That is, Poetry may be real, and powerful, and
lovely, and true... But the term "Poetry" does not describe actual
phenomena that can be materially defined and observationally defined. Poetry is
a term by which one compares a given experience with that grand collection of
all else which people have ever referred to as poetic.
We must note quickly, this is not purely
subjective. The biological classification of the Platypus as a mammal, or the
definition of a virus as a non-living entity, these established positions are
at least somewhat subjective. But defining "Poetry" today now goes
far beyond one personal or official opinion on record. Today, to defend
something as poetry, there are certain allowable comparisons one may invoke.
It's not a science. It's not art, either. That is, writing and reciting and
evoking poetry is art, but determining what qualifies as "poetry" is
neither science nor art. Actually, it's a lot more like politics, or the US
justice system. There's a process of appeal ruled by an elaborate system of
conventions. Therefore, my worst limerick qualifies as a poem if and only if I
can get some other people to agree that it does.
In other words, Poetry is an idea that isn't
also a thing. It's a complex ideological construction. Real, but not actual.
What else is like this?
Democracy and Communism are also ideas, and yet
never actual things. To illustrate this, look at present day China.
China, today, is not quite as it was fifty years
ago, nor as it will yet become, probably. Is China becoming as much democratic
as communist? Time will tell. Political Scientists use terms like these to
define and refine ways of comparing large scale human government but we know
these terms are merely linguistic tools, made as flexible as need be from one
era to another. That's partly because the entire field of Political Science is
yet another "complex ideological construction". And thus, so are
Democracy and Communism.
While the evolving political situation in China
requires some description in order to be studied, these terms - like most
language, in fact - are only capable of referring to a general collection of
previous descriptions. The China of 2014 is not very much like the Athens of
Pericles, the Rome of Augustus, or the America of Obama - each of which are
wildly different versions of this "thing" we call Democracy. And
that's precisely the point. Democracy isn't a thing. It's purely an idea, one
used for referencing a complex ideological collection of occasions when
politics received this description.
The idea is not a thing, but a way to compare
things.
For the ultimate example, consider numerical
values. What is "two"? You cannot show me "two". You can
only show me two-of-something. It was human experiences of seeing similar
things near one another that instigated the need for this concept: two. But the
numerical value of two - and perhaps arguably all of mathematics - is nothing
but an idea. Two is an abstraction. Numerical value may usefully describe
actual things, but numerical value itself is an idea that is not a thing.
DO MORE WITH TWO
MORE WITH MATH
MEASUREMENT
"
But the most relatable example of all probably
has to be Love. You've had experiences which were powerful and real and you've
poetically referred to them as "love". So love describes actual
phenomena, but love cannot be held, seen, measured, or even defined.
We may say "God is Love" but we cannot say "Love is God". ETC...
......
Time is an idea. Not a thing. Our systems for
measuring time, and accounting for past "times", are complex
ideological constructions.
********************************************************
C'est fini?
Write the next chapter for me, if you like.
Anon, then...